Don't mind the gap

The Third Way needs a theory of fairness
August 19, 1999

The third way needs a theory of fairness. These days most of us are rather confused about those grand old phrases-"social justice," "equality of opportunity," "meritocracy." New Labour is no exception.

Almost everyone agrees that equality of outcome is out, and equality of opportunity and meritocracy are in. The trouble is that the latter are as unattainable as the former without trampling over many of the values we cherish. Even if inheritance tax is raised and private schools closed, you cannot ban people from handing on the "cultural capital" which is what matters in shaping life chances. And the majority of us with only moderate talents know that a real meritocracy would be an uncomfortable place in which to live.

We want something gentler than the social Darwinism of the right, but rooted in today's realities. The economic reality is that capitalism is creating a more diverse income spectrum and a wider gap between top and bottom. The best that centre-left governments can do is to slow the speed at which the gap increases, through mild redistribution. Indeed this is what has happened in Britain over the past two years. There has been more redistribution, but at the same time the inequality gap has continued to widen.

So, what's the problem? The old fixation with the "gap" is the problem. A third way theory of fairness should state that the gap does not matter-or at least that it matters less than the life chances of the people at the bottom. If those are rising steadily then it does not matter that the rich are getting even richer. People once assumed that redistribution would automatically narrow the gap. But redistribution now coexists with a growing income gap.

"Gap" thinking is also based on a defunct zero-sum idea of wealth creation. In a 19th-century mining village it was clear that the mine owner's wealth in a sense caused the poverty of the miners. Other than the odd sweat shop, that is not the case today. The poverty of the poor does not create the richness of the rich and vice versa. Bill Gates has not amassed a fortune of $150 billion by exploiting the poor of Seattle.

Public policy might still want to distinguish between the "good" rich (meritocratic)-whom Tony Blair likes to praise-and the "bad" rich (inherited from ancestors in the slave trade). The point is that the rich, and what, if anything, to do about them (should they help fund the arts or universities?) is a separate issue from improving the conditions of the worst off.

"Gap" thinking is embedded in our language. For example, there is much anxiety about health inequality. But if equality is what we want it is easy to achieve: make the rich sicker. In fact we want to improve the health of the poor. (In education it seems that many people really do want to make the rich stupider, by closing their schools.)

When New Labour had been in power for a year, an American friend asked me how it was doing. I asked how he would measure success, and he replied, "What are they doing for the talented kid from a poor family?" I said it had abolished the assisted places scheme.

There is quite a wide consensus on what a fair society looks like. It would not be a full meritocracy, but it would have a high degree of status equality and a reasonably fluid social order-satisfying that concern for the talented poor. It would have wide variations in income, but would be underpinned by high and rising minimum standards of health, education and welfare. This has the benefit of being popular, attainable and measureable-unlike cotton-wool phrases about equality of opportunity.n