Human conditions

John Gray is a tragic fatalist. Steven Pinker believes in a progressive science of humanity. Are either of them right?
October 19, 2002

Where once the idea of human nature was treated with suspicion, today there is barely a human activity for which someone does not have an evolutionary account. A key figure in bringing about this change has been the psychologist Steven Pinker. Books such as The Language Instinct and How the Mind Works have established Pinker's reputation both as one of the finest science writers of his generation and as a swashbuckling champion of evolutionary psychology and the computational theory of mind.

Pinker, however, remains unconvinced that there has been such an intellectual transformation. Human nature, he insists, remains "a modern taboo." It's a taboo "that distorts our science and scholarship, our public discourse and our day-to-day lives." In his new book, The Blank Slate, Pinker seeks to to restore balance to the discussion of what it is to be human.

The "modern denial of human nature," he argues, is rooted in three beliefs: "the blank slate," the "noble savage" and the "ghost in the machine." According to the blank slate view, human infants acquire all their knowledge socially. The ideology of the noble savage suggests that humans are naturally born good, and that society corrupts them. The "ghost in the machine" is the term that the philosopher Gilbert Ryle gave to Descartes's view of the mind as an immaterial spirit distinct from the physical world.

Many social scientists cling to these three beliefs-what philosophers call empiricism, romanticism and dualism-because, Pinker says, they are gripped by a politically inspired dread of human nature. The Blank Slate unpicks this dread, in particular the worry that scientific theories of human nature can legitimise inequality, undermine moral responsibility, and lead to nihilism. Not only are "claims about human nature less dangerous than many people think," Pinker argues, but "the denial of human nature can be more dangerous than people think."

There is much to admire about The Blank Slate, not least the wit and panache with which it is written. I agree with Pinker's dismissal of most of the political and moral fears about the idea of human nature. The Blank Slate, however, is more than simply an argument about the importance of human nature. For Pinker, the blank slate view is not so much an incorrect view of human behaviour as a general-purpose bogeyman responsible for every bad idea in the 20th century-or, at least, every one that Pinker dislikes. Among the horrors laid at its door are totalitarianism, relativism, progressive education, modernist art, postmodern literature, atonal music, bad public housing, liberal criminology, poor child-rearing practices and hostility to biotechnology.

Pinker wants not just to demolish the bad ideas to which we still cling, but also to lay the foundations for a new vision of what it is to be human, to provide a "scientific explanation for the tragedy of the human condition." The trouble with this approach is that humans are not simply natural beings and cannot be understood as if we were. Our history is as much about our emancipation from nature as our embodiment in it.

The difficulty in understanding humans in a purely naturalistic way can be seen in Pinker's own argument. The key to a science of human nature, he argues, is the distinction between biological facts and human values. Human values are not rooted in nature, but arise in spite of nature. Pinker rejects both the "naturalistic fallacy" (the belief that if something is natural, it must be good) and the "moralistic fallacy"-the claim that if a trait is moral, it must be found in nature. This separation of nature and values allows Pinker to reject the criticism that evolutionary psychology provides an excuse for bad behaviour. There is a difference, he points out, between explanation and exculpation. To explain a phenomenon is not to accept it as morally good. Men may be naturally promiscuous, but that does not necessarily make promiscuity right, nor does it necessarily excuse the behaviour of promiscuous men. "Nature is what we are put on this earth to rise above," Pinker suggests, echoing Katharine Hepburn in The African Queen.

But this separation of nature and values raises new problems. Human values, presumably, do not float down from the sky; how then do they originate if not through "natural selection and neurophysiology," which Pinker considers the basis of all human thoughts and behaviour? Pinker argues that some innate faculties "may endow us with greed or lust or malice, but others may endow us with sympathy, foresight, self-respect... and an ability to learn from our own experiences and those of our neighbours." Nature, in other words, has endowed us with both good and bad propensities, and particular values arise from the clash of these propensities. This suggests that values are rooted in nature. It is difficult to distinguish this argument from that which Pinker condemns as the "moralistic fallacy." The primatologist Frans de Waal suggests in his book The Ape and the Sushi Master that thinkers like Pinker "want to have it both ways: human behaviour is an evolutionary product except when it is hard to explain."

No one-not even the blankest of blank slate advocates-denies that human thoughts and behaviours are the products of brain processes. But this is not the same as explaining where those thoughts and values come from. Why, for instance, have we come to believe that slavery is wrong and the idea of equal worth good? Pinker says that everyone feels "revulsion... toward discrimination and slavery," because it is in our nature to reject such treatment: "No one likes being enslaved. No one likes being humiliated."

For most of human history, though, slavery was regarded as natural as individual freedom is today. Only in the past 200 years have we begun to view the practice with revulsion. Why? Partly because of the political ideas generated by the Enlightenment, partly because of the changing economic needs of capitalism, and partly because of the struggles of the enslaved and the oppressed. To understand human values such as the belief in equal worth, we need to explore not so much human psychology as human history, society and politics.

Another way of putting this is that human nature is not simply natural. An inherently ambiguous concept, human nature means both that which expresses the essence of being human and that which is constituted in nature. In non-human animals, the two meanings are synonymous. What dogs, bats or sharks typically do as a species, they do because of natural selection. But this is not so in humans. The human essence-what we consider to be the common properties of our humanity-is shaped as much by our history as by our biology.

A good illustration of the historicity of the human essence is, paradoxically, the universality of great art. Art, Steven Pinker argues, is "in our genes," because nature endows us with an innate aesthetic sense. Great artists, such as Shakespeare or Beethoven, are appreciated across cultures and over time because their work taps into the some of universal features of human nature. Modernism, on the other hand, has been an aesthetic failure, Pinker suggests, because it developed "out of a militant denial of human nature."

Not only is this a crass view of modernism, but also a misunderstanding of Shakespeare's genius. Shakespeare did not simply articulate universal themes of love, lust and power; he also helped fashion a new vision of what it is to be human. Shakespeare's characters speak to us in an entirely different way because, unlike previous literary figures, they possess self-consciousness as we do. The kind of sensibility that Shakespeare brought to the stage, his near-contemporaries Rembrandt and Vermeer worked into a canvas, while Descartes gave it philosophical form. What we can see here is the development of the modern sense of subjectivity, and of the individual as a rational agent. Human emotions may be furnished by evolution, but the self that possesses those emotions was forged by history. That's why Shakespeare's work is both universal and contingent. It is universal because, today, whether we live in Britain or in Japan, we are able to recognise in his characters the workings of our own self. It is contingent because this concept of the self was not given by nature but made in history.

Humans possess a dual character, as both biological beings and historical agents. The very development of the scientific method has exacerbated this paradox of being human. It seems crucial to think of humans as conscious agents capable of rational thought and collective action if science itself is to advance. But such a view appears to be an obstacle to the realisation of a fully naturalistic view of man. By making humans into conscious agents we seem to separate them off from the rest of nature, and hence to suggest that the language of natural science cannot fully encompass our humanness.

Pinker, like many contemporary thinkers, attempts to resolve this conundrum by trying to understand human subjectivity as we might any other natural process. The self, he suggests, is just a description of a brain process. To say someone is morally responsible for their actions is to say that they possess a "functioning brain system that can respond to public contingencies of punishment." Moral responsibility resides in certain parts of the brain that are able to inhibit violent or criminal behaviour "by anticipating how the community would respond to it." To invoke the self in any other sense, Pinker suggests, is to re-introduce the ghost into the machine.

Since brain processes underlie all thoughts and actions, so the self in some sense must be a brain process. But to suggest that the self is simply a brain process is a bit like Margaret Thatcher's infamous claim that "there is no such thing as society: there are individual men and women and there are families." Individuals and families constitute society. But society has an existence beyond those individuals and families.

Similarly, with selves. We cannot point to a self in the way that we can point to a neuron. But that does not mean that neurons have a reality, and selves don't. As neurobiologist Joseph LeDoux put it (Prospect, August 2002): "My assertion that synapses are the basis of personality does not assume that your personality is determined by synapses... Synapses are simply the brain's way of receiving, storing and retrieving our personalities, as determined by all the psychological, cultural and genetic factors."

Selves are expressive of the human capacity to act as self-conscious subjects, not simply to exist as natural objects. All animals have an evolutionary past. Only humans make history.

There is, however, a widespread reluctance today to acknowledge this idea of humans as transformative beings. "Humans think they are free, conscious beings," John Gray writes in his provocative new book, Straw Dogs, "but in truth they are deluded animals." Straw Dogs is a trenchant critique of humanism, the belief that humans "can free themselves from the limits that frame the lives of other animals" and be "masters of their own destiny." For Gray this is an absurd delusion. "We do not speak of a time when whales or gorillas will be masters of their destinies," he asks. "Why then humans?" Only, he suggests, because humanists deny what Darwin taught us: that humans are animals and, like all animals, we are "only currents in the drift of genes."

Like Pinker, Gray begins with the argument that humans can be understood simply as natural beings. Unlike Pinker, he dispenses with any attempt to reconcile such a view with humanist notions of freedom and morality. Instead, Gray accepts that freedom is an "illusion" and the self a "chimera."

The western rationalist tradition is doomed because it rests on the faith that "through science humankind can know truth-and so be free." But, Gray argues, "if Darwin's theory of natural selection is true this is impossible." Darwinian processes are driven, not by the need to ascertain the truth, but to survive and reproduce. Accordingly, "the human mind serves evolutionary success, not truth." Indeed, "in the struggle for life, a taste for truth is a luxury," even a "disability." Science, Gray suggests, reveals that "humans cannot be other than irrational."

But science itself is a product of our befuddled, irrational, stone age minds. If we cannot trust such minds to discover truths about the world, how can we accept the verities of science-including the theory of evolution? The logic of Gray's argument undermines our confidence in its own veracity. For if we are just another animal, then we cannot place any trust in the claim that we are just another animal. We are only able to do science because of our ability to transcend our evolutionary heritage.

Gray's argument rests on a single proposition: because humans evolved like all other species, so we continue to be limited like all other species. This, however, is to commit what is often called the genetic fallacy-to believe that because the origin of x is A, so x is A. In other words, that because Homo sapiens began as dumb animals, so we must remain dumb animals. Gray, like Pinker, seems blind to the historicity of human nature. Unlike Pinker, he is willing to take such blindness to its logical conclusion.

Straw Dogs is written not as a conventional book, but as a string of loosely connected thoughts. It is less a rational argument than the expression of a mood. But, given the rapture with which the book has been greeted, it is clearly a mood that afflicts many. A former Thatcherite who became disillusioned with the social and economic changes that Thatcherism wrought, Gray has increasingly come to question the very value of the political process.

"Those who struggle to change the world," he writes, are merely seeking "consolation for a truth they are too weak to bear." Their "faith that the world can be transformed by human will is a denial of their own mortality." We're all going to die anyway, seems to be the argument, so why bother with grand schemes of social change? "The freest human being," Gray suggests, "is not one who acts on reasons he has chosen for himself, but one who never has to choose"-a sentiment that might appear not simply anti-humanist but also disturbingly authoritarian.

Pinker would undoubtedly reject Gray's misanthropic anti-humanism. Indeed, he suggests that his aim is to create a new, "biologically aware humanism." Yet the logic of Pinker's argument about human nature takes him in the same political direction as Gray. In the most important chapter of The Blank Slate, Pinker explores the relationship between evolutionary psychology and contemporary politics. He rightly dismisses the argument that sociobiology and evolutionary psychology are inherently reactionary. But, he acknowledges, "the new sciences of human nature really do resonate with assumptions that historically were closer to the right than to the left."

Drawing on the work of the American economist Thomas Sowell, Pinker suggests that there are two broad visions of what it is to be human: the tragic and the utopian. The tragic vision recognises that humans are "inherently limited in knowledge, wisdom and virtue, and all social arrangements must acknowledge those limits." Such limitations highlight the importance of tradition. "Religion, the family, social customs, sexual mores and political institutions are a distillation of time-tested techniques that let us work around the shortcomings of human nature." It is a vision associated with Thomas Hobbes, Edmund Burke, Adam Smith, Friedrich Hayek, Milton Friedman, Isaiah Berlin and Karl Popper-and now John Gray.

In the utopian vision, by contrast, "psychological limitations are artefacts that come from our social arrangements, and we should not allow them to restrict our gaze from what is possible in a better world." Traditions are regarded as "the dead hand of the past, the attempt to rule from the grave," and hence must be subject to the scrutiny of reason. Only in this fashion have we rid ourselves of practices such as absolute monarchy, slavery and patriarchy "that were once thought to be rooted in human nature." It's a vision Pinker attributes to Rousseau, Thomas Paine, John Kenneth Galbraith and Ronald Dworkin.

"The new sciences of human nature," Pinker suggests, "vindicate some version of the tragic vision and undermine the utopian outlook." Science has revealed the primacy of family ties, the limited scope of communal sharing, and the universality of violence, dominance and ethnocentrism. It has shown human nature to be fixed, human beings to be flawed and human politics to be constrained by the inadequacies of the human psyche. Since "our moral sentiments, no matter how beneficent, overlie a deeper bedrock of selfishness," Pinker suggests, "we should not aim to solve social problems like crime or poverty, because in a world of competing individuals one person's gain may be another person's loss. The best we can do is to trade off one cost against another." Or, as John Gray puts it, "The good life is not found in dreams of progress, but in coping with tragic contingencies."

Evolutionary psychology has certainly thrown light on many aspects of human behaviour, from autism to sexual desire. But it has not revealed humans to be innately ethnocentric or selfish, nor that crime and poverty are ineradicable aspects of the human condition. It is, rather, the barbaric history of the 20th century that has left many people disillusioned about what it means to be human. Every impression that man makes upon the world, many have come to believe, is always for the worse. "For the first time since 1750," Michael Ignatieff wrote (Prospect, October 1999) "people experience history running not forwards, from savagery to civilisation, but backwards to barbarism."

The result, as Straw Dogs so strikingly reveals, has been a growth of anti-humanism, a despair about human capacities, disillusionment with ideas of social transformation, a view of human reason as a force for destruction rather than for betterment. In this process, utopianism has become a dirty word, standing for the hubristic belief that human reason can solve human problems, a belief that, many feel, can only lead to totalitarianism.

The consequence of all this has been the increased acceptance that we should limit our political horizons, that we should seek to manage rather than to overcome problems, and that we should look to science to explain why we cannot do certain things, rather than to politics to see how we can.

"To try and do something which is inherently impossible," the conservative philosopher Michael Oakeshott argued, "is always a corrupting enterprise." Oakeshott, Pinker suggests, sums up the dangers of transgressing the limits revealed by evolutionary psychology. But without such transgression is historical progress possible? And what could be more corrupting than accepting as inevitable problems that we might be able to tackle were we to attempt the impossible? As Pinker himself puts it, for utopians, "the existence of suffering and injustice presents us with an undeniable moral imperative. We don't know what we can achieve until we try, and the alternative of resigning ourselves to these evils as the way of the world, is unconscionable."