Politics

Against pragmatism

The vapid philosophy of modern politics

December 29, 2012
article header image

Politicians, commentators, academics—everyone loves the word “pragmatic.” Tony Blair told us on his election in 1997 that what counts is not “outdated ideology” but “what works.” David Cameron famously wrote that he doesn’t “believe in ‘isms’” because “words like communism, socialism, capitalism and republicanism all conjure up one image in [his] mind: extremism.” Earlier this year, Nick Clegg eagerly urged a group of business leaders that the Liberal Democrats would be “sensible and centrist; pragmatic—not dogmatic—at all times.” Over in the US, one of the Democrats’ most effective strategies in the November election was to portray the Republicans as out of touch, crippled by their anti-pragmatic moralism.

Modern politicians—taking their cues from advertising and business—tend to use words which come attached with an aura of positive buzz, often without having a grip on what they actually mean. “Pragmatism” is a classic example. In this case, however, the harm done goes beyond the annoyance caused to pedants and opponents of “political mumbo-jumbo.” Rather, it allows politicians to subtly stifle dissent, and causes us to neglect the most fundamental questions about what our society ought to look like.

Talk of “pragmatism,” especially in Britain, is a part of a narrative that proclaims that we have reached an era of post-ideological politics. But the term is extremely slippery, and the first problem with this cult of pragmatism is that no one seems willing to pin down exactly what they mean by “pragmatic.”

One possibility is that political pragmatism means finding the most effective means to achieving one’s goals. This reading, however, makes the virtue of pragmatism too trivial. In this sense of “pragmatic,” there is no necessary opposition between being pragmatic and being ideological. Even people driven by ideology can be concerned about actually realising their ideological values, rather than merely shouting about them.

Another possible interpretation: “pragmatism” means sacrificing moral aspirations for something else. But what exactly is the something else? It can’t be one’s own personal political gain—when Clegg and Cameron claim to be pragmatists, they don’t intend to convey that they will do anything to save their own skin (even if that may be true).

Perhaps the best interpretation is that pragmatists put concern for ordinary people’s well-being and an efficient socioeconomic system (“what works”) ahead of highfaluting moral ideals. Yet this remains highly problematic. The notion of “what works” is amorphous and vague. One can only assess whether something is working against some kind of a standard for what a well-functioning society looks like; for what it is that you want to work and how. As an economist might put the point, you have to have a utility function to maximise; you can’t just maximise.

Is a society “working” if GDP rises steadily but citizens are drastically unequal? What about if people of different races and religions have different access to opportunities and goods? These questions are ineliminably moral, and must be answered in detail before we can have a useable notion of “what works.” The attempt to find some value-neutral standpoint from which to assess what works—the aspiration for an escape from ideology altogether—is an impossible one. Deciding how to weigh up different social benefits and harms is hard; it goes to the core of what we want our society to be like. But these questions are just made harder by reducing a vast swathe of distinct and often competing considerations to a single, sweeping judgment of “what works.”

The error here is not just a philosophical one. When politicians talk about what works, they make tacit assumptions about various moral questions concerning the proper aims of public policy. But by presenting themselves as “non-ideological pragmatists,” they get away with leaving these assumptions unarticulated and undefended. And so we get a particular value-laden agenda—often, though not always, that of the ruling class—smuggled in, under the banner of anodyne pronouncements about the need to sometimes make compromises or to be sensitive to empirical evidence.

At its worst, this can amount to making a set of value-assumptions seem like incontestable and ineradicable features of the world; to what the sociologist Max Weber called the “routinisation” of value. Those who oppose a particular agenda are characterised as “living in the past’ or as failing to recognise the facts of the modern world. Likewise, talk of “possibility” is frequently used to delimit the range of political options, without it being made clear in what sense and why a particular course of action is supposedly “impossible.”

The master of this rhetoric was Tony Blair. Politics, for Blair, was—in the chilling phrase that he used in speaking about cooperation between European countries—“not about left or right, but the future and the past, and even strength or weakness.” And here he is in 2005, discussing his reasons for favouring a criminal justice system that allows the police to circumvent due process:

“We are trying to fight 21st century crime—anti-social-behaviour, drug-dealing, binge-drinking, organised crime—with 19th century methods, as if we still lived in the time of Dickens. The whole of our system starts from the proposition that its duty is to protect the innocent from being wrongly convicted. Don't misunderstand me. That must be the duty of any criminal justice system. But surely our primary duty should be to allow law-abiding people to live in safety.” For Blair, what divided people who supported such measures from those who didn’t was not a disagreement of values—about whether the punishment of potentially innocent individuals could be justified by the scale of the threat to the public—but rather the difference between someone living in the present and someone living in the past. His own view is presented as if it were a simple consequence of the fact that we are living in the 21st century. But Blair’s opponents did not support the principle of innocent until proven guilty because they disagreed with Blair about the extent of binge-drinking or drug-dealing; they supported it because they believed in the right not to be punished without receiving a fair hearing.

In this respect, the claim to be non-ideological is often, to paraphrase the critical theorist Slavoj Žižek, itself deployed in service of an ideological agenda. Blair was not a cold, calculating political operator with no ethical qualms or attachments. When he latched on to a moral narrative that he could believe in—as with the Iraq war —he could be gripped by the almost terrifying fervour of a true believer. It’s just that he used language—brilliantly, and dangerously—to try to make people believe that there was no space from which to oppose him.

His legacy lives on. It can be deployed in service of conservatism just as much as in service of radical reform, and this is amplified in times of economic trouble. Cameron, Osborne, and to some extent Clegg have elided questions about the burdens of austerity measures, and how they have been distributed across different social classes, by implicitly characterising their opponents as head-in-the-sand, “unrealistic” idealists failing to acknowledge that something needed to be done about the deficit. Yet that is simply not the question in play when intelligent critics wonder if the burden of austerity measures could not have fallen more squarely on the rich. Clegg, in the same recent speech, again provides a striking example, proclaiming—as if it were some sort of heroically straight-talking admission of what no one else will say—that “bluntly, with the economy still fragile, this is not the time for dogma.” In this way, the vague language of “pragmatism” attempts to justify the status quo without providing any kind of substantive argument.

Whereas the old “ideologues” were at least honest about their agenda, the new “pragmatists” do not even tell us what theirs is. The language of pragmatism is thus a far cry from “straight-talking”; rather, it is a way of depriving citizens of the language in which to voice dissent. If we are all pragmatists now, then we have lost our vision of what we want our political system to be like—of how we want it to “work.”